Un análisis inferencialista de la co-autoría de artículos científicos

  1. Jesús Zamora-Bonilla 1
  2. Javier González de Prado Salas 1
  1. 1 Universidad Nacional de Educación a Distancia, Madrid, España
Aldizkaria:
Revista española de documentación científica

ISSN: 0210-0614 1988-4621

Argitalpen urtea: 2014

Zenbakien izenburua: La colaboración científica

Alea: 37

Zenbakia: 4

Mota: Artikulua

DOI: 10.3989/REDC.2014.4.1145 DIALNET GOOGLE SCHOLAR lock_openSarbide irekia editor

Beste argitalpen batzuk: Revista española de documentación científica

Laburpena

Co-authorship is very common in most areas of science and has grown as the complexity of research has increased the need for scientific collaboration. But plural authorship tends to complicate the attribution of merit to individual scientists, which is the basis of scientific evaluation. I argue that collaboration does not necessarily entail co-authorship, though in many cases the latter is an option that the individual scientists might not choose, at least in principle: individually authors might separately publish their own contribution to a collaborative project in which they had taken part, or papers could explicitly state what contribution each individual author had made. I ask, hence, why it is that scientists prefer to ‘pool’ their contributions instead of keeping them separate if they are pursuing, amongst other things, individual recognition. My answer, following an inferentialist approach to scientific knowledge, is based on the view of the scientific paper as a piece of argumentation rather than as a piece of knowledge.

Erreferentzia bibliografikoak

  • Beaver, D. (2001). Reflections on scientific collaboration (and its study): past, present, and future, Scientometrics, 52, (3), 365-377. http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1014254214337
  • Biagioli, M. (1999). Aporias of Scientific Authorship: Credit and Responsibility in Contemporary Biomedicine, in M., Biagioli, ed., The Science Studies Reader, New York, London, Routledge, pp. 12-31.
  • Birnholtz, J. (2006). What does it mean to be an author? The intersection of credit, contribution and collaboration in science. Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology, 57, 1758-1770. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/asi.20380
  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it Explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Brandom, R. (2000). Articulating reasons: An introduction to inferentialism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Chompalov, I.; Genuth, J.; Shrum, W. (2002). The organization of scientific collaborations. Research Policy, 31, 749-767. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S0048-7333(01)00145-7
  • Coase, R. (1937). The Nature of the Firm. Economica, 4.16: 386–405. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0335.1937.tb00002.x
  • Coase, R. (1960). The Problem of Social Cost. Journal of Law and Economics, 3, 1-44. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/466560
  • Fallis, D. (2006). The epistemic costs and benefits of collaboration. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 44, 197-208. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.2041-6962.2006.tb00039.x
  • Glaenzel, W.; Schubert, A. (2004). Analysing scientific networks through co-authorship, in: Henk F., Moed et al., ed., Handbook of Quantitative Science and Technology Research. The Use of Publication and Patent Statistics in Studies of S&T Systems, Dordrecht, Boston, London, Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 257-276.
  • Goldman, A.; Whitcomb, D. (2010). Social Epistemology: Essential Readings, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
  • González de Prado Salas, J.; Zamora Bonilla, J. (2014). Collective actors without collective minds: an inferentialist approach. Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Publicado on-line 20/02/2014.
  • Hull, D. (1988). Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226360492.001.0001
  • LaFollette, M. C. (1992). Stealing into print: fraud, plagiarism, and misconduct in scientific publishing. University of California Press.
  • Laudel, G. (2001). Collaboration, creativity and rewards: why and how scientists collaborate. International Journal of Technology Management, 22, (7), 762-781. http://dx.doi.org/10.1504/IJTM.2001.002990
  • Laudel, G. (2002). What do we measure by co-authorships?. Research Evaluation, 11,(1), 3-15. http://dx.doi.org/10.3152/147154402781776961
  • Powell, W. W. (1990). Neither market nor hierarchy. Research in Organizational Behavior, 12, 295-336.
  • Rolin, K. (2010). Group justification in science", Episteme, 7, (3), 215-231. http://dx.doi.org/10.3366/epi.2010.0204
  • Thagard, P. (2006). "How to collaborate: procedural knowledge in the cooperative development of science", The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 44, 177-196. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.2041-6962.2006.tb00038.x
  • Wittgenstein, L. (1988). Investigaciones Filosóficas. Barcelona: Crítica. Traducción de A. García Suárez y U. Moulines.
  • Wray, K. B. (2002). The epistemic significance of collaborative research. Philosophy of Science, 69, (1), 150-168. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/338946
  • Wray, K. B. (2006). Scientific authorship in the age of collaborative research. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 37, 505-514. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2005.07.011
  • Wuchty, S.; Jones, B. F.; Uzzi, B. (2007). The increasing dominance of teams in production of knowledge. Science, 316, (5827), 1036–1039. http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.1136099
  • Zamora Bonilla, J. P. (2002). Scientific Inference and the Pursuit of Fame: A Contractarian Approach. Philosophy of Science, 69, 300-23. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/341055
  • Zamora Bonilla, J. P. (2006). Science as a Persuasion Game. Episteme, 2, 189-201. http://dx.doi.org/10.3366/epi.2005.2.3.189
  • Zamora Bonilla, J. P. (2007). Science Studies and the Theory of Games. Perspectives on Science, 14, 639-71.
  • Zamora Bonilla, J. P. (2010). What games do scientists play? Rationality, objectivity, and the social construction of scientific knowledge. EPSA Epistemology and Methodology of Science: Launch of the European Philosophy of Science Association (M. Suárez, ed.) pp. 323-332. Springer. Amsterdam.
  • Zamora Bonilla, J. P. (2011). Rationality in the social sciences: bridging the gap. The SAGE Handbook of the Philosophy of Social Science (eds. Ian Jarvie and Jesús Zamora-Bonilla). pp: 721-738. SAGE. London.